Romantic irony as aesthetic skepticism. On Hegel’s critique of the idea of “transcendent poetry”
DOI:
https://doi.org/10.17533/udea.ef.14989Keywords:
Irony, poetry, absolute, RomanticismAbstract
To understand Hegel’s debate against the concept of Romantic irony proposed by Friedrich Schlegel, it is imperative to detail the si rong relation between Negativity, Skepsis and irony. New light can be shed upon the liaisons between the Philosophy of irony and the Philosophy of the Absolute ift he closeness and distance of the inner Skeptic st rategies developed by Schlegel and Hegel are considered. For the latter, Schlegel's irony is a manifestation of an absolute, infinite Negativity: a character of aesthetic Skepsis. For Schlegel himself, it is the "supreme and purest Skepsis". By no means can the Skepticism be incorporated amidst the constant fluctuations of "self-creation and self-destruction ", amidst the eternal switching between discourse and counter discourse, thought and counter-thought. The attempt to reunify poetry and philosophy by means ofa “transcendental poetry-" has the same Achilles heel as the Ancient Pyrrhonism -oscillating between narration and discourse, trapped between them, it starves like Buridan donkey. Those ironists stay in the pure Negativity and their endless and longing deed resembles a fruitless conversation. For Hegel, the program of the early Romanticism moves between two extremes: yawning tedium and vital, critic and skeptic creativity.
Downloads
Downloads
Published
How to Cite
Issue
Section
Categories
License
Copyright (c) 2002 Estudios de Filosofía
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-ShareAlike 4.0 International License.
Authors who publish with this journal agree to the following terms:
1. The Author retains copyright in the Work, where the term "Work" shall include all digital objects that may result in subsequent electronic publication or distribution.
2. Upon acceptance of the Work, the author shall grant to the Publisher the right of first publication of the Work.
3. The Author shall grant to the Publisher a nonexclusive perpetual right and license to publish, archive, and make accessible the Work in whole or in part in all forms of media now or hereafter known under a Creative Commons Attribution-NoCommercia-ShareAlike (CC BY-NC-SA 4.0), or its equivalent, which, for the avoidance of doubt, allows others to copy, distribute, and transmit the Work under the following conditions: (a) Attribution: Other users must attribute the Work in the manner specified by the author as indicated on the journal Web site;(b) Noncommercial: Other users (including Publisher) may not use this Work for commercial purposes;
4. The Author is able to enter into separate, additional contractual arrangements for the nonexclusive distribution of the journal's published version of the Work (e.g., post it to an institutional repository or publish it in a book), as long as there is provided in the document an acknowledgement of its initial publication in this journal;
5. Authors are permitted, and Estudios de Filosofía promotes, to post online the preprint manuscript of the Work in institutional repositories or on their Websites prior to and during the submission process, as it can lead to productive exchanges, as well as earlier and greater citation of published work (see The Effect of Open Access). Any such posting made before acceptance and publication of the Work is expected be updated upon publication to include a reference to the Estudios de Filosofía's assigned URL to the Article and its final published version in Estudios de Filosofía.