Feeling the past: beyond causal content
DOI:
https://doi.org/10.17533/udea.ef.n64a09Keywords:
memory, temporal experience, percepction, causation, timeAbstract
Memories often come with a feeling of pastness. The events we remember strike us as having occurred in our past. What accounts for this feeling of pastness? In his recent book, Memory: A self-referential account, Jordi Fernández argues that the feeling of pastness cannot be grounded in an explicit representation of the pastness of the remembered event. Instead, he argues that the feeling of pastness is grounded in the self-referential causal content of memory. In this paper, I argue that this account falls short. The representation of causal origin does not by itself ground a feeling of pastness. Instead, I argue that we can salvage the temporal localization account of the feeling of pastness by describing a form of egocentric temporal representation that avoids Fernández’s criticisms.
Downloads
References
Bechlivanidis, C. & Lagnado, D. A. (2013). Does the “why” tell us the “when”? Psychological Science, 24(8), 1563–1572. https://doi.org/10.1177/0956797613476046
Bechlivanidis, C. & Lagnado, D. A. (2016). Time reordered: causal perception guides the interpretation of temporal order. Cognition, 146, 58–66. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2015.09.001
Boyle, A. (2020). Remembering events and representing time. Synthese, 1–20. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02896-6
Buhusi, C. V. & Meck, W. H. (2005). What makes us tick? Functional and neural mechanisms of interval timing. Nature Reviews. Neuroscience, 6(10), 755–765. https://doi.org/10.1038/nrn1764
Burge, T. (1979). Individualism and the mental. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 4(1), 73–122. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1475-4975.1979.tb00374.x
Byrne, A. & Hilbert, D. R. (2003). Color realism and color science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 26(1), 3–21. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X03000013
Callender, C. (2017). What makes time special? Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198797302.001.0001
Chen, L., & Vroomen, J. (2013). Intersensory binding across space and time: a tutorial review. Attention, Perception, & Psychophysics, 75(5), 790–811. https://doi.org/10.3758/s13414-013-0475-4
Cunningham, D. W., Billock, V. A. & Tsou, B. H. (2001). Sensorimotor adaptation to violations of temporal contiguity. Psychological Science, 12(6), 532–535. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9280.d01-17
De Brigard, F. (2014). Is memory for remembering? Recollection as a form of episodic hypothetical thinking. Synthese, 191(2), 1–31. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-013-0247-7
Dretske, F. (1997). Naturalizing the mind. MIT Press. https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/4872.001.0001
Earman, J. (1972). Notes on the causal theory of time. Synthese, 24(1), 74–86. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00540142
Evans, G. (1982). The varieties of reference. Oxford University Press.
Fernández, J. (2019). Memory: a self-referential account. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780190073008.001.0001
Fernández, J. (2020). Self-referential memory and mental time travel. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 11(2), 283–300. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-019-00453-w
Grunbaum, A. (1967). Modern science and Zeno’s paradoxes. George Allen & Unwin.
Grush, R. (2000). Self, world and space: the meaning and mechanisms of ego-and allocentric spatial
representation. Brain and Mind, 1(1), 59–92. https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1010039705798
Heron, J., Hanson, J. V. M. & Whitaker, D. (2009). Effect before cause: supramodal recalibration of sensorimotor timing. PLOS ONE, 4(11), e7681. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0007681
Hoerl, C., Lorimer, S., McCormack, T., Lagnado, D. A., Blakey, E., Tecwyn, E. C. & Buehner, M. J. (2020). Temporal binding, causation, and agency: developing a new theoretical framework. Cognitive Science, 44(5), e12843. https://doi.org/10.1111/cogs.12843
Lewis, D. (1976). The paradoxes of time travel. American Philosophical Quarterly, 13(2), 145–152. Michaelian, K. (2016). Mental time travel: episodic memory and our knowledge of the personal past. MIT Press. https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/10591.001.0001
Michotte, A. (1955). La Perception de la causalité. Les Etudes Philosophiques, 10(2), 308–309.
Perrin, D. (2018). A case for procedural causality in episodic recollection. In K. Michaelian, D. Debus & D. Perrin (Eds.), New Direction in the Philosophy of Memory (pp. 33–51). Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315159591-3
Perrin, D., Michaelian, K. & Sant’Anna, A. (2020). The phenomenology of remembering is an epistemic feeling. Frontiers in Psychology, 11, 1531. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2020.01531
Rankin, M. L. & McCormack, T. (2013). The temporal priority principle: at what age does this develop? Frontiers in Psychology, 4. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00178
Reichenbach, H. (1957). The philosophy of space and time (1st English Ed. edition). Dover Publications.
Rolfs, M., Dambacher, M. & Cavanagh, P. (2013). Visual adaptation of the perception of causality. Current Biology, 23(3), 250–254. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cub.2012.12.017
Scholl, B. J. & Tremoulet, P. D. (2000). Perceptual causality and animacy. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4(8), 299–309. https://doi.org/10.1016/S1364-6613(00)01506-0
Sekuler, R., Sekuler, A. B. & Lau, R. (1997). Sound alters visual motion perception. Nature, 385(6614), 308–308. https://doi.org/10.1038/385308a0
Stetson, C., Cui, X., Montague, P. R. & Eagleman, D. M. (2006). Motor-sensory recalibration leads to an illusory reversal of action and sensation. Neuron, 51(5), 651–659. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuron.2006.08.006
Strawson, P. F. (1964). Individuals: an essay in descriptive metaphysics. Routledge.
Suzuki, K., Lush, P., Seth, A. K. & Roseboom, W. (2019). Intentional binding without intentional action. Psychological Science, 30(6), 842–853. https://doi.org/10.1177/0956797619842191
Tye, M. (2000). Consciousness, color, and content. MIT Press. https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/2110.001.0001
Published
How to Cite
Issue
Section
Categories
License
Copyright (c) 2021 Gerardo Viera
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-ShareAlike 4.0 International License.
Authors who publish with this journal agree to the following terms:
1. The Author retains copyright in the Work, where the term "Work" shall include all digital objects that may result in subsequent electronic publication or distribution.
2. Upon acceptance of the Work, the author shall grant to the Publisher the right of first publication of the Work.
3. The Author shall grant to the Publisher a nonexclusive perpetual right and license to publish, archive, and make accessible the Work in whole or in part in all forms of media now or hereafter known under a Creative Commons Attribution-NoCommercia-ShareAlike (CC BY-NC-SA 4.0), or its equivalent, which, for the avoidance of doubt, allows others to copy, distribute, and transmit the Work under the following conditions: (a) Attribution: Other users must attribute the Work in the manner specified by the author as indicated on the journal Web site;(b) Noncommercial: Other users (including Publisher) may not use this Work for commercial purposes;
4. The Author is able to enter into separate, additional contractual arrangements for the nonexclusive distribution of the journal's published version of the Work (e.g., post it to an institutional repository or publish it in a book), as long as there is provided in the document an acknowledgement of its initial publication in this journal;
5. Authors are permitted, and Estudios de Filosofía promotes, to post online the preprint manuscript of the Work in institutional repositories or on their Websites prior to and during the submission process, as it can lead to productive exchanges, as well as earlier and greater citation of published work (see The Effect of Open Access). Any such posting made before acceptance and publication of the Work is expected be updated upon publication to include a reference to the Estudios de Filosofía's assigned URL to the Article and its final published version in Estudios de Filosofía.