The reception of Aristotle’s theory of chance in Alexander of Aphrodisias’ De Fato
DOI:
https://doi.org/10.17533/udea.ef.11621Keywords:
Aristotle, Alexander, chance, first moverAbstract
this paper deals with the reception and transformation of Aristotle’s theory of chance and causality in one of the fundamental works of ancient aristotelism: Alexander of Aphrodisias’ De Fato. Ross suggests a continuity between Aristotle and Alexander in some of the most important tenets of Alexander’s proposal. Ross points out some of the most significant differences between the two philosophers in the context of a more general discussion on the relation between the physical world and the metaphysical entities. According to Ross, Alexander introduced some notions into the Aristotelian philosophy, such as “fate” and “providence”, which are entirely alien to Aristotle’s original theses and diverge from the words of the Master in more than one occasion, even though he attributes to him his own doctrine. Finally, Ross attempts to show that there is a tension between the traditional reading of Metaphysics XII –inspired in Alexander– and some theses of Alexander’s De Fato. The view that the First Mover presents itself as something desirable and understandable to the first heaven, which moves in a circle to imitate the actuality of that which is presented as desireable and whose only activity is thinking of itself, is inspired, according to Ross, precisely Alexander.
Downloads
References
Ediciones y traducciones de textos antiguos y medievales
DE AFRODISIA, A. On Fate. R. W. Sharples (ed.). Duckworth, 2003.
DE AFRODISIA, A. Quaestiones 1.1-2.15. R. W. Sharples (ed.). Cornell University Press, 1992.
DE AFRODISIA, A. Quaestiones 2.16-3.15. R. W. Sharples (ed.). Cornell University Press, 1994.
DE AFRODISIA, A. Sobre el destino. Trad. de José Molina y Ricardo Salles. Promanuscrito, 2008.
DE AFRODISIA, A. Traité de la providence. P. Thillet (ed.). Verdier, 2003.
DE AQUINO, S. T. In duodecim libros Metaphysicorum Aristotelis expositio. Edición y estudio de R. M. Spiazzi. Marietti, 1964.
ARISTÓTELES. Física I-II. Trad. y comentario de Marcelo Boeri. Biblos, 1993.
ARISTÓTELES. Física VII-VIII. Trad. y comentario de Marcelo Boeri. Biblos, 2003.
ARISTOTLE. Metaphysica. Ed. y comentario de D. Ross. Oxford University Press, 1924.
ARISTOTLE. Physica. Ed. y comentario de D. Ross. Oxford University Press, 1936. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/actrade/9780198141099.book.1
FILOPÓNO. On Aristotle’s Physics 2. Trad. de A. Lacey. Duckworth, 1993.
SIMPLICIO. On Aristotle’s Physics 2. Trad. de D. B. Fleet. Duckworth, 1997.
TEMISTIO. In Aristotelis Metaphysicorum librum XII paraphrasis hebraice et latine. Reimer, 1903.
Secundaria
BERTI, E. “Il movimento del cielo in Alessandro di Afrodisia”, en: Brancacci, A. (ed.). La filosofia in età imperiale. Le scuole e le tradizioni filosofiche. Napoli, 2000, pp. 225-243.
BERTI, E. “La Causalità del Motore Immobile secondo Aristotele”, en: Gregorianum 83/4, 2002, pp. 637-654.
BERTI, E. “Metaphysics L 6”, en: Frede, M. y Charles, D. Symposium Aristotelicum. Aristotle’s Metaphysics Lambda. Oxford University Press, 2000, pp. 181-206. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198237648.003.0007
BOERI, M. “Una aproximación a la noción aristotélica de Dios”, en: Tópicos: Revista de Filosofía de Santa Fe 6, 1999, pp. 63-89. DOI: https://doi.org/10.14409/topicos.v0i6.7381
BRADSHAW, D. “A new look at the Prime Mover”, en: Journal of History of Philosophy 39/1, 2001, pp. 1-22. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2003.0074
BRANCACCI, A. (ed.). La filosofia in età imperiale. Le scuole e le tradizioni filosofiche. Napoli, 2000.
BROADIE, S. “Que fait le premier moteur d’Aristote?”, en : Revue philosophique de la France et de l’étranger 183, 1993, pp. 375-411.
ELDERS, L. Aristotle’s theology. A commentary on book lambda of the Metaphysics. Assen, 1972.
FREDE, M. AND CHARLES, D. (eds.) Symposium Aristotelicum. Aristotle’s Metaphysics Lambda. Oxford University Press, 2000. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198237648.001.0001
GILL, M. AND LENNOX, J. (eds.). Self motion: from Aristotle to Newton. Princeton, 1994.
JUDSON, L. “Heavenly motion and the Unmoved Mover”, en: Gill, M. – Lennox, J. Self motion: from Aristotle to Newton. Princeton, 1994, pp. 155-171. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/9781400887330-011
KOSMAN, A. “Aristotle’s Prime Mover”, en: Gill, M. – Lennox, J. Self motion: from Aristotle to Newton. Princeton, 1994, pp. 135-153. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/9781400887330-010
MENN, S. “Aristotle and Plato on God”, en: Review of Metaphysics 45/3, 1992, pp. 543-573.
NATALI, C. “Causa motrice e causa finale nel libro Lambda della Metafisica de Aristotele”, en: Méthexis X, 1999, pp. 105-123. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1163/24680974-90000274
REALE, G. La metafísica di Aristotele. Nápoli, Luigi Loffredo, 1968.
ROSS, A. Dios, eternidad y movimiento en Aristóteles. Pamplona, EUNSA, 2007.
SHARPLES, R. “Alexander of Aphrodisias on Divine Providence: Two Problems”,en: The Classical Quarterly 32-1, 1982, pp. 198-211. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838800023004
SORABJI, R. Aristotle transformed: the ancient commentators and their influence. Duckworth, 1990.
Downloads
Published
How to Cite
Issue
Section
Categories
License
Copyright (c) 2009 Alberto Ross Hernández
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-ShareAlike 4.0 International License.
Authors who publish with this journal agree to the following terms:
1. The Author retains copyright in the Work, where the term "Work" shall include all digital objects that may result in subsequent electronic publication or distribution.
2. Upon acceptance of the Work, the author shall grant to the Publisher the right of first publication of the Work.
3. The Author shall grant to the Publisher a nonexclusive perpetual right and license to publish, archive, and make accessible the Work in whole or in part in all forms of media now or hereafter known under a Creative Commons Attribution-NoCommercia-ShareAlike (CC BY-NC-SA 4.0), or its equivalent, which, for the avoidance of doubt, allows others to copy, distribute, and transmit the Work under the following conditions: (a) Attribution: Other users must attribute the Work in the manner specified by the author as indicated on the journal Web site;(b) Noncommercial: Other users (including Publisher) may not use this Work for commercial purposes;
4. The Author is able to enter into separate, additional contractual arrangements for the nonexclusive distribution of the journal's published version of the Work (e.g., post it to an institutional repository or publish it in a book), as long as there is provided in the document an acknowledgement of its initial publication in this journal;
5. Authors are permitted, and Estudios de Filosofía promotes, to post online the preprint manuscript of the Work in institutional repositories or on their Websites prior to and during the submission process, as it can lead to productive exchanges, as well as earlier and greater citation of published work (see The Effect of Open Access). Any such posting made before acceptance and publication of the Work is expected be updated upon publication to include a reference to the Estudios de Filosofía's assigned URL to the Article and its final published version in Estudios de Filosofía.